Sceptical scenario arguments:
For example:
This week:
G. E. Moore argues against the sceptic's first premise, the claim that you cannot know that you are not a BIV.
He thought you can know that you are not a BIV.
Moore's argument:
Moore's argument reverses the sceptic's:
So whose first premise should we prefer?
Maybe we are more certain of Moore's.
But why think this certainty is of any epistemological significance?
Compare Hume's observation, last week, that we are psychologically incapable of giving up our belief in the external world.
A natural reaction to this is, "So what? How can that be epistemologically significant?"
The sceptic gives this argument for her premise:
Where does Moore think this goes wrong?
Moore says that, while he cannot prove that the dreaming scenario does not obtain, he thinks that he nevertheless has conclusive evidence that it does not.
So he seems to deny the third claim, that to know that BRAIN IN A VAT does not obtain, one needs to be able to rule out the possibility that it does.
One reason why Moore's response may seem unsatisfying: while he seems to reject the third claim, he gives us no explanation as to WHY it should be rejected.
(Compare Moore here with the reliablist, below.)
According to Nozick, S knows that P IFF
More briefly, S knows that P IFF S has a true belief that P which TRACKS THE TRUTH.
In meeting the third condition, S's belief that P is said to be SENSITIVE.
The third and fourth conditions are COUNTERFACTUALS.
To check whether they hold, we need to consider how things would be in certain possible situations.
"If I had dropped this glass, the water in it would have spilled"
This seems true because in the CLOSEST possible situations in which I drop the glass (those most similar to the actual sitation), the water spills.
It doesn't seem to matter that there are possible situations in which I drop the glass but the water does not spill - someone is hiding under the table, the water freezes.
Those situations are less close.
More generally, it seems that a counterfactual holds IFF, in the closest possible situations in which the antecedent is true, the consequent is also true:
"If it were the case that P, it would be the case that Q"
In these terms, Nozick's view is that S knows that P IFF
What's this got to do with the BIV argument?
Do you know the proposition that you are not a BIV (who is being deceived by a deranged scientist)?
Nozick: No. Even if you truly believe that you are not a BIV, you don't know it.
The closest possible situations in which it is false (in which you are a BIV) are ones in which, because you are being deceived, things seem to you to be the same as they actually seem. In those situations, you still believe that you are not a BIV.
So your belief is not sensitive.
Do you know the proposition that that you have hands?
Nozick: Yes, assuming that you truly believe that you have hands.
The closest possible situations in which it is false (in which you don't have hands) are ones in which, say, you have been in an industrial accident. In those situations, you don't believe that you have hands.
So Nozick's third condition is met. Your belief is sensitive.
And the fourth condition? If the proposition that you have hands were true, would you have believed it?
The closest possible situation in which it is true (in which you do have hands) is the actual situation. In that situation, you believe that you have hands. So Nozick's fourth condition is met too.
So Nozick's fourth condition is met as well.
According to Nozick, then, the sceptic's second premise is false: even though you don't (and in fact cannot) know that you are not a BIV, you can know that you have hands.
We saw the sceptic's argument for this premise last week:
Nozick accepts premise 1. (Homework: explain why!)
But he denies premise 2.
So Nozick thinks there are counterexamples to EPISTEMIC CLOSURE:
If you know that P entails Q, and you can know that P, then you can also know that Q.
Notice that, unlike Moore, Nozick explains not just where he thinks the sceptic's argument fails, but WHY. His account of knowledge is playing a crucial role.
According to reliablists, S knows that P IFF
Do you know the proposition that you have hands?
Reliablist: Yes, assuming that you truly believe that you have hands.
Your belief that you have hands is produced by a reliable process: perception.
Do you know the proposition that you are not a BIV?
Reliablist: Yes!
Your belief that you are not a BIV is produced by applying a reliable process, deductive inference, to your belief that you have hands, which is itself produced by a reliable process.
According to reliablists, then, the sceptic's first premise is false: you CAN know that you are not a BIV.
Consider again the sceptic's argument for this:
Like Moore, the reliablist rejects premise 3. To know that a sceptical scenario does not obtain, you do not need to be able to rule out the possibility that it does, i.e. prove that it does not.
But unlike Moore, the reliablist offers an explanation as to WHY premise 3 fails: an account of knowledge on which it requires only reliably produced true belief.
Here are two (connected) worries one might raise about Nozick's and the reliablist's responses to the sceptic.
In different ways, both Nozick and the reliablist argue that your belief that you have hands constitutes knowledge, given the assumption that you have hands.
Doesn't this beg the question against the sceptic?
No. The sceptic doesn't deny that your belief that you have hands is true. She argues that it cannot constitute knowledge.
But if the reliablist's or Nozick's analyses of knowledge are correct, your belief that you have hands can constitute knowledge - and does constitute knowledge if it is true.
Another way of putting this: both Nozick and the reliablist try to show that it is possible that we do know that we have hands. But they try to do this without proving that we know we have hands.
So both Nozick and the reliablist allow for the possibility that we know that we have hands even if we do not know that we know that we hands.
So they both deny the KK PRINCIPLE:
One knows that P only if one knows that one knows that P.
On both Nozick's and the reliablist's analyses, whether S's true belief that P constitutes knowledge that P depends on factors that may be external to S's mind:
This is EXTERNALISM about knowledge.
By contrast, consider: S knows that P IFF
On this analysis, whether S's true belief that P constitutes knowledge that P depends only on factors that are internal to S's mind.
This is INTERNALISM about knowledge.
Laurence Bonjour raises a potential problem for externalism about knowledge:
Norman, under certain conditions that usually obtain, is a completely reliable clairvoyant with respect to certain kinds of subject matter. He possesses no evidence or reasons of any kind for or against the general possibility of such a cognitive power, or for or against the thesis that he possesses it. One day Norman comes to believe that the President is in New York City, though he has no evidence either for or against this belief. In fact the belief is true and results from his clairvoyant power, under circumstances in which it is completely reliable.
Bonjour (1980) 'Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge', p. 62.
Norman's true belief is both sensitive and reliably produced.
But does Norman know that the President is in New York City?
We might insist that Norman does know that the President is in New York City.
But what if we amend the case, and give Norman lots of evidence that he is not clairvoyant?
Moore's runs the sceptic's argument in reverse, and denies the sceptic's first premise, the claim that we cannot know that we are not BIVs.
If we are dissatisfied with Moore's response, that may be at least partly because he doesn't explain WHY the sceptic's argument fails.
Nozick denies the sceptic's second premise, the claim that we cannot know we have hands if we cannot know that we are not BIVs.
He therefore denies EPISTEMIC CLOSURE.
This follows from his account of knowledge as true belief that TRACKS THE TRUTH.
Reliablists deny the sceptic's first premise, the claim that we cannot know that we are not BIVs.
This follows from their account of knowledge as true belief that is RELIABLY PRODUCED.
Both Nozick and the reliablist offer EXTERNALIST accounts of knowledge and deny the KK PRINCIPLE.
Laurence Bonjour's CLAIRVOYANT case presents a challenge for externalism.