Ethics

Below are readings and essay questions for tutorials in Ethics. Many of the readings are available online, and all are easily obtained from the college or other libraries in Oxford, but if you are struggling to get hold of anything, email me, as I have PDF copies of nearly everything.

The default plan is to cover the TUTORIAL TOPICS, focusing mainly on normative ethics and some key contributions in the history of philosophy. After a week on consequentialism, the main approach to normative ethics, and its critics, we turn to the early modern roots of the contemporary debate, looking at Hume and Kant. As we will see, these first few weeks raise important questions about practical reason and the normative status of morality—questions that we take up in more detail in looking at the challenge to morality posed by psychological and rational egoism. We’ll then return to the contemporary scene, bringing together what we’ve learnt, and look at two different nonconsequentialist approaches to normative ethics, contractualism and virtue ethics, before finishing off with an introduction to contemporary metaethics. The plan is not set in stone, however. Those of you who have studied them beforehand may wish to drop either the first or last week’s topics, and either spread your study of Hume over two weeks, or look at something else altogether. To that end, I have also listed a range of OTHER TOPICS. If you would like to cover any of these—or something else—let me know, and we’ll see what we can do. Topics that you might have covered in the first year Moral Philosophy course and might want to leave for self-study in vacations are marked with a dagger (†).

The reading for each topic is divided into two parts. In writing your tutorial essay, focus on the CORE READING, using as a guide the more introductory texts marked with a star (*) and any Faculty lectures on the topic—the lectures may be available online via Canvas, and are a good indication of what might come up in the exams. You can look at the FURTHER READING, as well as anything else of relevance in the Faculty reading list, when exploring topics in more depth during later vacations and revision.

The current version of this reading list was put together in light of using previous incarnations in teaching Ethics to undergraduates in Oxford over the years. I’m grateful to various friends and colleagues for advice and discussion, especially Nadine Elzein, Edward Harcourt, Ulrike Heuer, Chris Jay, Ed Lamb, Mike Martin, Véronique Munoz-Dardé, Stefan Sienkiewicz, and Tom Sinclair. If you’d like to use the list for teaching, please feel free. Feedback and corrections are gratefully received.

Latest update: 7th January 2023.

TUTORIAL TOPICS

  1. Consequentialism and Its Critics
  2. Hume’s Ethics
  3. Kant on Moral Motivation
  4. The Categorical Imperative
  5. Egoism: Why Be Moral?
  6. Contractualism
  7. Virtue Ethics
  8. Moral Realism: Problems

OTHER TOPICS: METAETHICS

  1. Error Theory and Fictionalism
  2. Non-Cognitivism
  3. Naturalism
  4. Nonnaturalism
  5. Moral Relativism

OTHER TOPICS: REASONS and MOTIVES

  1. Practical Reasoning
  2. Motivational Internalism

OTHER TOPICS: NORMATIVE ETHICS

  1. Well-Being†
  2. Equality
  3. Rights†

OTHER TOPICS: MORAL PSYCHOLOGY

  1. Free Will and Moral Responsibility†
  2. Conscience, Guilt, and Shame
  3. Blame and Standing to Blame

OTHER TOPICS: APPLIED ETHICS

  1. Doing and Intending Harm
  2. Non-Human Animals
 

VACATION READING and TEXTBOOKS

If you are thinking about whether to take Ethics, or have decided to do so and want to do some preliminary reading over the vacation beforehand, take a look at some of the following introductory textbooks. (Note that earlier editions of these, where applicable, are often much cheaper second-hand and usually just as good.)

*Driver, Julia (2006) Ethics: The Fundamentals (Blackwell).

*Rachels, James and Stuart Rachels (2018) The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 9th ed. (McGraw Hill).

*Shafer-Landau, Russ (2021) The Fundamentals of Ethics, 5th ed. (OUP).

For consolidation in later vacations, you might want something a little more advanced. The following are recommended. They are no substitute for working through the CORE READING and FURTHER READING, however. To do well in any philosophy paper, you have to work through the details, not just the summaries.

*Timmons, Mark (2012) Moral Theory: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Rowman & Littlefield).

*Wiggins, David (2006) Ethics: Twelve Lectures on the Philosophy of Morality (Penguin).

I also recommend that you take the opportunity to familiarise yourself beforehand, if you haven’t already, with these four classics of moral philosophy—the exam will offer you opportunities to display knowledge of them. We’ll be focusing on Hume’s Treatise and Kant’s Groundwork, but all of them are essential reading.

Aristotle (c. 350 B.C.E.) Nicomachean Ethics. Various editions, inc. Hackett, 3rd edition, trans. and ed. by Terence Irwin (Hackett, 2019).

Hume, David (1739/40) A Treatise of Human Nature, Books II and III. Various editions, inc. Oxford Philosophical Texts edition, ed. by David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton (OUP, 2000).

Kant, Immanuel (1785) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. Various editions, inc. Cambridge Texts, revised edition, trans. and ed. by Mary Gregor and Jens Timmermann (Cambridge UP, 2012).

Mill, John Stuart (1861) Utilitarianism. Various editions, inc. Oxford Philosophical Texts edition, ed. by Roger Crisp (OUP, 1998).

ANTHOLOGIES and COLLECTIONS

While most of the readings can be obtained online, it’s useful to have good anthologies and collections of papers to hand, so as to be able to read around the subject a bit more widely. The following are all recommended, containing many of the key readings and more besides, and are often referenced below.

Cahn, Steven, and Peter Markie, eds. (2016) Ethics: History, Theory, and Contemporary Issues, 6th ed. (OUP). Referred to below as Cahn and Markie.

Copp, David, ed. (2006) The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory (OUP). Referred to below as Copp.

Darwall, Stephen, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton, eds. (1997) Moral Discourse & Practice: Some Philosophical Approaches (OUP). Referred to below as Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton.

Fisher, Andrew and Simon Kirchin, eds. (2006) Arguing about Metaethics (Routledge). Referred to below as Fisher and Kirchin.

LaFollette, Hugh, and Ingmar Persson, eds. (2013) The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory 2nd ed. (Blackwell). Referred to below as LaFollette and Persson.

Raphael, D. D. (David Daiches), ed. (1969) British Moralists: 1650-1800 (OUP, 2 Volumes). Referred to below as Raphael.

Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey, ed. (1988) Essays in Moral Realism (Cornell UP). Referred to below as Sayre-McCord.

Shafer-Landau, Russ, ed. (2012) Ethical Theory: An Anthology, 2nd ed. (Wiley-Blackwell). Referred to below as Shafer-Landau.

Sher, George, ed. (2012) Ethics: The Essential Readings (Routledge). Referred to below as Sher.

TUTORIAL TOPICS

1. CONSEQUENTIALISM and ITS CRITICS

TOP

In setting the essay question and readings for this topic, I’ve assumed you’re familiar with utilitarianism and consequentialism more generally from the Moral Philosophy component of the first year course. If not, let me know, and I will suggest a different essay question and set of readings, possibly splitting the topic into two.

ESSAY QUESTION

What are the most serious objections to consequentialism? Are any of them decisive? Can (and must) nonconsequentialists give an adequate account of how it can sometimes be right to do what’s not best?

CORE READING

If you haven’t encountered them already, focus on the following classic texts on this week’s issue. (If you have encountered them already, then you can take a look at some of the FURTHER READING instead.) Williams (1973) presents his influential integrity objection. Nozick (1974) raises and attempts to defuse a problem for nonconsequentialists, one which has come to be known as the paradox of deontology. Railton (1984) sets out and responds to the objection—related to Williams’—that consequentialism is, in an important way, alienating.

Williams, Bernard (1973) ‘A Critique of Utilitarianism’ in J. J. C. (Jack) Smart and Bernard Williams (1973) Utilitarianism: For & Against (Cambridge UP). Reprinted in Samuel Scheffler, ed. (1988) Consequentialism and its Critics (OUP), referred to below as Scheffler, as well as in both Cahn and Markie and Sher.

Nozick, Robert (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Blackwell), pp. 26-33 (pp. 38-42 of the online version). Reprinted as ‘The Rationality of Side Constraints’ in Shafer-Landau and as ‘Side Constraints’ in Scheffler.

Railton, Peter (1984) ‘Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality’ in Philosophy & Public Affairs 13(2), pp. 134–171. Reprinted in Shafer-Landau, Scheffler, and Sher.

By way of a guide, try any of the following more introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Kagan, Shelly (1989) The Limits of Morality (OUP), Ch. 1, esp. pp. 24-32. Introduces the demandingness objection—to which Kagan endorses an extremist response—and the paradox of deontology.

*Scheffler, Samuel (1988) ‘Introduction’ in Scheffler. A concise but classic introduction to this week's issues, surveying the main objections to consequentialism and the main responses to the paradox of deontology.

*Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2003/19) ‘Consequentialism’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 Edition). A good overview of the main issues concerning consequentialism.

*Timmons, Mark (2012) Moral Theory: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Rowman & Littlefield), Ch. 5 and 6. A good textbook discussion of the issues surrounding both classic and contemporary consequentialism.

FURTHER READING

In thinking about this week’s topic in more depth, get hold of a copy of Scheffler and work through its contents, a series of classic papers that are invaluable in understanding the contemporary debate. Besides the Williams, it contains two other important criticisms of consequentialism: Rawls, in a selection from his A Theory of Justice, ‘Classical Utilitarianism,’ (also reprinted in Sher,) presents the influential objection that utilitarianism fails to respect the separateness of persons, while Nagel, in his ‘War and Massacre,’ presents a version of the objection that consequentialism is too permissive, entailing that acts that are, in fact, forbidden are permitted. In thinking about objections to consequentialism, however, the best place to start is perhaps with the dual of the last objection, the objection that it is too demanding, entailing that acts that are, in fact, at best optional are mandatory. In response, some argue that the extreme demands consequentialism is alleged to make are not unreasonable. Kagan, in the rest of his (1989), argues for this extremist response, as does Singer (1972)—a classic of applied ethics that all students doing this paper ought to read. Others deny that consequentialism makes the alleged demands, or can be reformulated in such a way as to avoid making them. Jackson (1991) is perhaps an example of the former response, denialism, while Railton’s indirect consequentialism, defended in Mason (1998), is perhaps an example of the latter, reformism. Other, more clearly reformist responses include rule consequentialism, defended by Hooker in his contribution to LaFollette and Persson (and reprinted in Shafer-Landau and Sher); satisficing consequentialism, criticised in Bradley (2006); and scalar consequentialism, defended in Norcross (2006). For critical discussion of extremism, denialism, and reformism, see Mulgan (2001). Williams’ objection is sometimes taken as a version of the demandingness objection, though you should think carefully about whether that’s the best way to understand it; Ch. 4 of Hurley (2009), raising issues about the normative status of morality that we’ll be looking at soon, is useful in this regard. Another interesting objection is the cluelessness objection, defended in Lenman (2000). After objections to consequentialism, think about the paradox of deontology. Again, Scheffler contains several classics. Besides the piece by Nozick, see Nagel’s ‘Autonomy and Deontology’, Foot’s ‘Utilitarianism and the Virtues,’ and Scheffler’s ’Agent-Centred Restrictions, Rationality, and the Virtues’. But perhaps the most important thing to look at is Kamm’s contribution to LaFollette and Persson—looking especially at her discussion of inviolability on pp. 272-6. As Foot’s article especially helps bring out, the flipside to the paradox of deontology is an argument for act consequentialism, based on the idea, roughly put, that it is always right to bring about the best. For more critical discussion of this, see Ch. 5 of Hurley (2009). For arguments for rule consequentialism, see Parfit (2011a) and Hooker’s piece in LaFollette and Persson.

Bradley, Ben (2006) ‘Against Satisficing Consequentialism’ in Utilitas 18(2), pp. 97–108.

Hurley, Paul (2009) Beyond Consequentialism (OUP).

Jackson, Frank (1991) ‘Decision-Theoretic Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection’ in Ethics 101(3), pp. 461–82.

Lenman, James (2000) ‘Consequentialism and Cluelessness’ in Philosophy and Public Affairs 29(4), pp. 342–70.

Mason, Elinor (1998) ‘Can an Indirect Consequentialist Be a Real Friend?’ in Ethics 108(2), pp. 386-93.

Mulgan, Tim (2001) The Demands of Consequentialism (OUP). Unavailable online. If you are unable to get hold of a physical copy from a library, email me.

Norcross, Alastair (2006) ‘Reasons Without Demands: Rethinking Rightness’ in Jamie Dreier, ed. Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory (Blackwell).

Parfit, Derek (2011a) On What Matters, Volume One (OUP), Ch. 16.

Singer, Peter (1972) ‘Famine, Affluence, and Morality’ in Philosophy & Public Affairs 1(3), pp. 229-43. Reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Shafer-Landau, and Sher.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

Can rule-consequentialists specify a compliance level at which candidate rules are to be assessed without falling prey to decisive objections to their view? (2022)

Can consequentialists make adequate sense of moral dilemmas? (2021)

‘Since just about all consequences of actions are unforeseen and unforeseeable, we are ignorant about which actions to perform if consequentialism is true.’ Is that so? What does your answer suggest about the truth of consequentialism? (2020)

EITHER
(a) ‘There exists no plausible theoretical account of how we could fail to be obligated to bring about the best available outcome whenever doing so is permissible. Therefore, the objection that consequentialism is too demanding is ineffective.’ Discuss.
OR
(b) ‘There exists no plausible theoretical account of how it could be wrong to harm others if we thereby bring about the best available outcome. Therefore, the objection that consequentialism is too permissive is ineffective.’ Discuss. (2019)

2. HUME’S ETHICS

TOP

Hume is a key figure in the history of moral philosophy, and in the history of utilitarian thought in particular. But understanding his work is crucial to fully appreciating a range of issues concerning Kant and practical reason. Note that, if you are skipping the first or last topics, you may wish to split your study of Hume over two weeks, postponing consideration of his views on justice and artificial virtues. If so, discuss this with me beforehand.

ESSAY QUESTION

What does Hume mean when he says that moral distinctions are not derived from reason? Are his arguments for this convincing? Is his alternative, sentimentalist account of moral assessment defensible? In particular, what problem do artificial virtues, like justice, raise for his account? Is his solution to it a satisfactory one?

CORE READING

Start by reading the most important parts of Hume’s Treatise:

Hume, David (1739/1740) A Treatise of Human Nature, Book II, Part 3, Section 3, ‘Of the Influencing Motives of the Will’, and Book III, ‘Of Morals’, especially: Part 1; Part 2, Sections 1 and 2; and Part 3, Section 1. Various editions, inc. Oxford Philosophical Texts edition, ed. by David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton (OUP, 2000). Relevant selections reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Raphael, Sher, and Shafer-Landau.

By way of a guide, try any of the following more introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Brown, Charlotte R. (2008) ‘Moral Rationalism, Sentimentalism, and Sympathy’ in Elizabeth S. Radcliffe, ed. A Companion to Hume (Blackwell), referred to below as Radcliffe. Doesn't cover Hume's treatment of justice, or virtues more generally, but a good introduction to his anti-rationalism and sentimentalism.

*Cohon, Rachel (2004/18) ‘Hume's Moral Theory’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 edition). A good overview of Hume's views, introducing some of the main interpretive issues.

*Garrett, Don (2015) Hume (Routledge), Ch. 8. A good, concise introduction to Hume's anti-rationalism, sentimentalism, and the natural and artificial virtues, as well as Hume's influence on contemporary debates.

*Norton, David Fate (2009) ‘The Foundations of Morality in Hume's Treatise’ in David Fate Norton and Jacqueline Taylor, eds. The Cambridge Companion to Hume, 2nd ed. (Cambridge UP), referred to below as Norton and Taylor. Another good overview of Hume's views, discussing, inter alia, the historical context.

If you are only studying Hume for one week, this will be more than enough to be getting on with. If you are splitting your study of him over two weeks, look also at some of the FURTHER READING suggested below. You might, e.g., look at Sturgeon’s paper in Ainslie and Butler, eds. (2018) and Abramson’s in Radcliffe for the first week, and Ch. 7 of Snare (1991) and Magri’s paper in Ainslie and Butler, eds. (2018) for the second.

FURTHER READING

In thinking about Hume’s ethics further, you might want to look at the rest of Books II and, especially, III of the Treatise, and will certainly want to look at the later Enquiry, Hume (1751/77), where he presents things a bit differently, foregrounding his positive account of virtue and vice, and relegating his case against moral rationalism to an appendix—Appendix 1. It also criticises egoism—see especially Appendix 2—a topic you will explore in more depth later. Hume himself thought it was “incomparably the best” of his writings. (Cahn and Markie and Raphael both reprint large parts of it.) The main issues to think about are (a) Hume’s account of the relation between reason and passion, (b) his criticisms of moral rationalism, (c) his sentimentalist account of moral assessment, and (d) his account of the artificial virtues, like justice. It is mainly the first and second issues that come up in past papers, but the others do appear on occasion. (Note that, while the examination regulations for the paper state that candidates will be given the opportunity to demonstrate first-hand knowledge of Hume’s writings, that doesn’t mean there will be questions explicitly about him, never mind his account of motivation or criticisms of rationalism.) In any case, all these aspects of Hume’s views are relevant to many of the issues we’re exploring this term, as well as various of the OTHER TOPICS—especially PRACTICAL REASONING, MOTIVATIONAL INTERNALISM, and FREE WILL and MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Mackie (1980) and Baillie (2000) are two good, accessible books on Hume’s ethics, both aimed at advanced undergraduates. Baier (1991), Snare (1991), and Cohon (2008) are more advanced treatments, but well worth the effort. Thinking ahead to future weeks, see also Korsgaard (1989) and the lectures on Hume in Rawls (2000), both listed in the FURTHER READING for KANT on MORAL MOTIVATION, and Foot (1972), a classic of contemporary moral anti-rationalism. You’ll also find good, up-to-date discussions in various handbooks and companions. See, for example, Penelhum’s paper in Norton and Taylor, as well as the papers by Abramson and Lecaldano in Part III and Radcliffe, Beauchamp, and Sturgeon in Part VI of Radcliffe, Sturgeon, Ainslie, and Magri in Ainslie and Butler, eds. (2018), and in Part III of Russell, ed. (2016).

Ainslie, Donald C. and Annemarie Butler, eds. (2018) The Cambridge Companion to Hume’s Treatise (Cambridge UP).

Baier, Annette (1991) A Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise (Harvard UP), Ch. 6 to 10.

Baillie, James (2000) Hume on Morality (Routledge), esp. Ch. 4 to 7.

Cohon, Rachel (2008) Hume's Morality: Feeling and Fabrication (OUP).

Foot, Philippa (1972) ‘Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives’ in The Philosophical Review 81(3), pp. 305–316. Reprinted in her (2002) Virtues and Vices (OUP), Cahn and Markie, Shafer-Landau, and Sher, as well as with an accompanying recantation in Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton.

Hume, David (1751/77) An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Various editions, inc. Oxford Philosophical Texts, ed. by Tom L. Beauchamp (OUP, 1998).

Mackie, J. L. (John Leslie) (1980) Hume's Moral Theory (Routledge), esp. Ch. III to VI.

Russell, Paul, ed. (2016) The Oxford Handbook of Hume (OUP).

Snare, Francis (1991) Morals, Motivation and Convention: Hume's Influential Doctrines (Cambridge UP).

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘Hume’s genealogy of morality is plausible, but it does not show that morality is binding.’ Discuss. (2022)

Can Hume explain why people should be motivated to act in accordance with ‘artificial’ virtues even when doing so is contrary to the general interest? (2021)

‘It’s true that reason is the slave of the passions, but it ought not to be.’ Discuss. (2020)

‘Rationality merely requires the efficient satisfaction of whatever it is that we ultimately want.’ Is that so? (2019)

3. KANT on MORAL MOTIVATION

TOP

Many think morality involves, not just doing the right thing, but doing it for the right reasons. Kant is often held to have a particularly austere account of this sort. We look at his account this week, our first of two on Kant.

ESSAY QUESTION

How, in Kant’s view, must an action be motivated in order for it to have “moral worth”? Is he right?

CORE READING

Start by reading the relevant parts of Kant’s Groundwork:

Kant, Immanuel (1785) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, Preface and §I. I recommend the Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy rev. edition, trans. and ed. by Mary Gregor and Jens Timmermann (Cambridge UP, 2012). Selections—either of alternative translations or the earlier, unrevised version of Gregor's—are also reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Shafer-Landau and Sher.

Then tackle both of the following classics of the contemporary literature on the topic:

Herman, Barbara (1981) ‘On the Value of Acting from the Motive of Duty’ in The Philosophical Review 90(3), pp. 359–382. Reprinted in her (1993) The Practice of Moral Judgement (Harvard UP)—this isn't available online; email me for a PDF if you have difficulty finding a copy in libraries—and in Cahn and Markie.

Arpaly, Nomy (2002) ‘Moral Worth’ in Journal of Philosophy 99(5), pp. 223–245. An extended version appears as Ch. 3 of her (2003) Unprincipled Virtue: An Inquiry into Moral Agency (OUP).

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Allison, Henry E. (2011) Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary (OUP), Part II, esp. Ch. 4. An excellent, if more advanced commentary on section I of the Groundwork.

*Darwall, Stephen (1998) Philosophical Ethics (Westview), Ch. 14. A good introduction to Kant's overall project in the Groundwork, and in section I in particular, briefly discussing his views on moral worth.

*Guyer, Paul (2007) Kant's Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (Continuum), Ch. 4. A good, clear and accessible introduction to the central aims and arguments of first section I of Kant's Groundwork.

*Johnson, Richard N. (2009) ‘Good Will and the Moral Worth of Acting from Duty’ in Thomas E. Hill, Jr., ed. The Blackwell Guide to Kant's Ethics (Blackwell), referred to below as Hill. An excellent introduction.

*Schneewind, Jerome B. (1992) ‘Autonomy, Obligation, and Virtue’ in Paul Guyer, ed. The Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge UP). An accessible introduction to Kant's moral philosophy.

FURTHER READING

One piece to prioritise in thinking more about Kant and moral motivation is Baron (1995), defending Kant from the objection that he places too much value on acting from duty, though warning against thinking of him as exclusively concerned with what he calls the moral worth of an action. Baron insists that he’s in fact more interested in character and virtue. Other pieces to prioritise include Markovits (2010), who takes a similar line to Arpaly in the CORE READING and argues that what matters for the moral worth of an action is that the agent act for the reasons that make the act is right—the reasons why it is right—rather than for the reason that it is right, and Sliwa (2016), who responds in defence of the view that moral motivation requires both a concern for doing what is right and knowledge that the action is right. For extended discussion of the issues, see also Stratton-Lake (2000). The background worry is that orthodox approaches in ethics, such as Kant’s, are overly austere, allowing little room for personal relationships and ordinary human motivations. For an influential discussion of Kant’s ethics, in particular, see Williams (1976), raising the objection that Kant’s account of moral motivation involves “one thought too many”. See also Langton (1992), connecting with issues we’ll come to with the topic, EGOISM: WHY BE MORAL?, and focusing on issues arising out of the correspondence between Kant and Maria von Herbert, who had written to Kant in a state of deep depression, seeking his advice. Less focused on Kant but also relevant are various of the papers reprinted in Crisp and Slote, eds. (1997). See especially Michael Stocker’s ‘The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories’ and Susan Wolf’s ‘Moral Saints’—the latter is also reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Shafer-Landau, and Sher. See also Foot’s ‘Virtues and Vices,’ offering a VIRTUE ETHICS perspective on issues of moral worth. For more on how this week’s topic connects with Kant’s wider aims in the Groundwork and later weeks’ topics, Korsgaard (1989) is very useful, as is Kerstein’s piece in Hill. Lastly, Rawls’ lectures on Kant, published in his (2000) are invaluable. The resurgence of interest in Kant’s ethics in the 70s and 80s was largely due to the influence of Rawls and his students, Barbara Herman, Christine Korsgaard, and Onora O’Neill, and his lectures are very helpful, both as a guide to Groundwork and in gaining a better understanding of Rawls’ influence on contemporary ethics. For this week’s topic, it is the first lecture on Kant that is the one that is most relevant.

Baron, Marcia (1995) Kantian Ethics Almost Without Apology (Cornell UP), Ch. 5.

Crisp, Roger and Michael Slote, eds. (1997) Virtue Ethics (OUP).

Korsgaard, Christine (1989) ‘Kant's Analysis of Obligation: The Argument of Foundations I’ in The Monist 72(3), pp. 311-340. Reprinted in her (1996) Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge UP).

Langton, Rae (1992) ‘Duty and Desolation’ in Philosophy 67(262), pp. 481–505. Reprinted in her (2009) Sexual Solipsism (OUP) and abridged as ‘Maria Von Herbert’s Challenge to Kant’ in Sher.

Markovits, Julia (2010) ‘Acting for the Right Reasons’ in The Philosophical Review 119(2), pp. 201–42.

Rawls, John (2000) Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy, ed. by Barbara Herman (Harvard UP). This isn't available online. If you have difficulty getting hold of it from libraries, email me.

Sliwa, Paulina (2016) ‘Moral Worth and Moral Knowledge’ in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93(2), pp. 393–418.

Stratton-Lake, Philip (2000) Kant, Duty and Moral Worth (Routledge), Ch. 1 to 4.

Williams, Bernard (1976) ‘Persons, Character, and Morality’ in Alice Rorty, ed. The Identity of Persons (University of California Press). Reprinted in his (1981) Moral Luck (Cambridge UP) and Sher.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

EITHER
(a) Can objections to Kant’s account of moral worth be addressed adequately by distinguishing between ways in which a person might be motivated by duty?
OR
(b) ‘How could exercising the freedom to choose…represent the renunciation of freedom? It could if this were analogous to the free choice of slavery. But how similar would [a] villain’s choice be to the choice of slavery?’ (DAVID WIGGINS) Do Kantians have a good response to these questions? (2022)

‘In the end, Kant’s ethics gives obligation to our loved ones only derivative value at best.’ How significant an objection to Kant’s ethics is this? (2021)

How should we account for special obligations to loved ones? (2018)

Is there a moral duty to do as one’s conscience dictates? (2017)

4. THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE

TOP

ESSAY QUESTION

Could either of Kant’s universal law formulations of the Categorical Imperative serve as the supreme principle of morality? Would it be a decisive objection to Kant’s moral philosophy if they could not?

CORE READING

Start by reading the relevant parts of Kant’s Groundwork:

Kant, Immanuel (1785) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, §§I and II. I recommend the Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy rev. edition, trans. and ed. by Mary Gregor and Jens Timmermann (Cambridge UP, 2012). Selections, either of alternative translations or the earlier, unrevised version of Gregor's, are reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Shafer-Landau and Sher.

Then tackle both of the following classics of the contemporary literature on the topic:

Korsgaard, Christine (1985) ‘Kant's Formula of Universal Law’ in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66(1/2), pp. 24-47. Reprinted in her (1996) Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge UP) and Shafer-Landau.

Wood, Allen (1999) Kant's Ethical Thought (Cambridge UP), Ch. 3.

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Allison, Henry E. (2011) Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary (OUP), Part III, esp. Ch. 7. An excellent, if more advanced commentary on section II of the Groundwork.

*Darwall, Stephen (1998) Philosophical Ethics (Westview), Ch. 15. A good introduction to Kant's various formulations of the Categorical Imperative, as well as wider issues concerning his normative ethics.

*Galvin, Richard (2009) ‘The Universal Law Formulas’ in Thomas Hill Jr., ed. The Blackwell Guide to Kant's Ethics (Blackwell), i.e. Hill. A good introduction to the issues, focused on the FUL and FULN.

*Guyer, Paul (2007) Kant's Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (Continuum), Ch. 5. A good, clear and accessible introduction to the aims and arguments of section II of the Groundwork, discussing the FUL/FLN.

*Hill, Thomas E. Jr. (2006) ‘Kantian Normative Ethics’ in Copp. Reprinted in his (2012) Virtue, Rules, and Justice: Kantian Aspirations (OUP). An excellent introduction to this week's issues.

FURTHER READING

In thinking about this topic in more depth, focus first on the formulas of universal law (FUL) and universal law of nature (FLN). Influenced by Rawls and O’Neill—see lecture II on Kant in Rawls (2000), listed as FURTHER READING for KANT on MORAL MOTIVATION, and O’Neill (2013)—many take these to summarise a decision procedure for determining whether or not an action is permissible, the so-called CI procedure, which involves identifying the maxim of an action, “universalizing” it, and testing to see whether the result gives rise to either a contradiction in conception or a contradiction in the will. So understood, the central question is whether there is any interpretation of the CI procedure that avoids counter-examples—either false positives (intuitively immoral maxims that pass the tests) or false negatives (intuitively permissible maxims that fail). In thinking about the issue, work through the fairly exhaustive (and somewhat exhausting) catalogue of interpretations and counter-examples in Ch. 12 of Parfit (2011a), listed as FURTHER READING for CONSEQUENTIALISM and ITS CRITICS. Other good pieces on the issues include: Wiggins (1987); Ch. 5 of O’Neill (1989); Nyholm (2015) and Kleingeld (2019), responding to Parfit; and Ch. 7 of Herman (1993), listed in the CORE READING for KANT on MORAL MOTIVATION. The essay question focuses on the FUL and FLN, but think also about Kant’s other formulations of the CI. Past papers often include questions relating to the formula of humanity (FH), which enjoins us to use humanity in ourselves and others always as an end in itself and never merely as a means. Is there any way of understanding the distinction here between using humanity as an end in itself and never merely as a means so that it has moral significance? Parfit (2011a) is again very useful, criticising a range of different interpretations of the FH in Ch. 9. See also: Ch. 2 of Hill (1992); Ch. 6 of O’Neill (1989) and Ch. 4 of Korsgaard (1996), defending a possible consent approach; Pallikkathayil (2010), criticising the possible consent approach and connecting the FH to Kant’s political philosophy; lecture III on Kant in Rawls (2000); Scanlon (2008); and Ch. 4 of Wood (1999), arguing that the FH only yields conclusions about duties on the basis of intermediate premises and a faculty of judgement irreducible to general rules—part of his campaign against treating Kant’s ethics as a kind of “ethical sausage machine”. Kerstein (2019) is a good survey of the issues, as is Dean’s contribution to Hill. Lastly, have a think about the formulas of autonomy (FA) and the kingdom or realm of ends (FRE). You’ll find relevant discussion of these in Ch. 3 of Hill (1992), Ch. 5 of Korsgaard (1996), Ch. 7 of O’Neill (1989), lecture IV on Kant in Rawls (2000), and Ch. 5 of Wood (1999)—while Holtmann’s contribution to Hill provides an accessible overview.

Hill, Thomas E. Jr. (1992) Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Theory (Cornell UP).

Kerstein, Samuel (2019) ‘Treating Persons as Means’ in Edward Zalta, ed. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 edition).

Kleingeld, Pauline (2019) ‘A Contradiction of the Right Kind: Convenience Killing and Kant’s Formula of Universal Law’ in The Philosophical Quarterly 69(274), pp. 64–81.

Nyholm, Sven (2015) ‘Kant’s Universal Law Formula Revisited’ in Metaphilosophy 46(2), pp. 280–99.

O'Neill, Onora (1989) Constructions of Reason (Cambridge UP).

— (2013) Acting on Principle: An Essay on Kantian Ethics, 2nd ed. (Cambridge UP).

Pallikkathayil, Japa (2010) ‘Deriving Morality from Politics: Rethinking the Formula of Humanity’ in Ethics 121(1), pp. 116–47.

Scanlon, T. M. (Tim) (2008) Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame (Harvard UP), Ch. 3.

Wiggins, David (1987) ‘Universalizability, Impartiality, Truth’ in his (2002) Needs, Values, Truth, 3rd ed. (OUP). This isn't available online. If you have difficulty getting hold of it from libraries, email me.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

Is there a way to interpret the principle that one ought never to treat anyone as a mere means that gives it non-derivative moral force and has intuitively compelling implications? (2021)

EITHER
(a) ‘If lying to a bank employee in order to secure a loan which I cannot pay back cannot serve as a law of nature, lying to my captor in order to secure my freedom from imprisonment also cannot. Yet while the former is impermissible, the latter is permissible. So, whether something can hold as a universal law of nature is neither here nor there when it comes to its deontological status.’ Is this a good argument?
OR
(b) What is the difference between treating someone as a means and treating them as a mere means? Does that difference matter, morally speaking? (2020)

What does it mean to treat humanity always as an end in itself and never as a mere means? Is this a plausible moral requirement? (2019)

Is there any important relation between being able to will one’s maxim as a universal law and treating humanity as an end in itself? (2018)

5. EGOISM: WHY BE MORAL?

TOP

So far, we’ve focused mainly on the content of morality. This week, we look at its normative status—an issue Kant takes up in the third section of the Groundwork—and the threat to it posed by various forms of egoism.

ESSAY QUESTION

How do psychological and rational egoism challenge morality? How, if at all, are these challenges to be met?

CORE READING

Start by reading the following classics on the topic:

Prichard, H. A. (Harold Arthur) (1912) ‘Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?’ in Mind 21(81), pp. 21-37. Reprinted in his (2002) Moral Writings, edited by Jim MacAdam (OUP) and in Cahn and Markie.

Williams, Bernard (1973) ‘Egoism and Altruism’ in his Problems of the Self (Cambridge UP). Alternatively, try his (1972) Morality: An Introduction to Ethics (Harper & Row), Ch. 1, which covers similar ground.

Blackburn, Simon (1998) Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning (OUP), Ch. 5. This doesn't seem to be available online. If you have difficulty getting hold of it from libraries, email me for a PDF.

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Deigh, John (2010) An Introduction to Ethics (Cambridge UP), Ch. 1 to 3. An accessible introduction to the apparent conflict between morality and self-interest and various attempts to address it, including Prichard's.

*Hills, Alison (2010) The Beloved Self: Morality and the Challenge from Egoism (OUP), Ch. 1 and 2. An excellent introduction to this week's issues. Ch. 5 and 11 are also recommended, if you have time.

*Shaver, Robert (2002/19) ‘Egoism’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2021 edition). A good, accessible introduction to the debates over the various forms of egoism.

*Timmons, Mark (2012) Moral Theory: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Rowman & Littlefield), Ch. 7.

FURTHER READING

The problem posed by rational egoism goes back at least as far as c. 380 B.C.E., and Plato’s Republic. At first pass, the worry is that, if rational egoism is true, and one only ever has reason to pursue one’s self-interest, then one doesn’t have reason to be moral unless it advances one’s self-interest. Some respond by arguing that morality does advance one’s self-interest, i.e. by arguing for some form of ethical egoism. For one strategy here, see Ch. 13 to 15 of Hobbes’ Leviathan (1651). For another—Plato’s own strategy in the Republic—see discussions of perfectionism in connection with WELL-BEING. But it’s not clear that any form of ethical egoism fully addresses the problem. As Prichard (1912) emphasises, if rational egoism is true, one’s reason for being moral can only be that it is in one’s self-interest, and so doesn’t seem to be of the right sort—one cannot do the right thing for the right reasons. It may be that the better option is therefore to reject rational egoism altogether. There are various strategies here. One, associated particularly with proponents of Humean conceptions of practical rationality, rejects rational egoism for an alternative account on which some of us, some of the time, have reason to be moral, even when it goes against our self-interest—though others conceivably might not. The piece by Williams in the CORE READING is a classic example. See also, in this connection, Foot (1972), listed above as FURTHER READING for HUME’S ETHICS. Others take a harder line, and try to show that all of us, all of the time, have reason to be moral—i.e. to provide a vindication of morality. (The likes of Raz (1999), who thinks that there is something suspect about the idea of an amoralist, are harder to place.) Hills, in the CORE READING, criticises various attempts to provide an ambitious vindication—i.e. one that would convince even the amoralist—in Ch. 5 and goes on to offer her own modest vindication in Ch. 11. Think about the ambitious vindications she criticises, especially Parfit (1984). You’ll find more discussion of Parfit in the pieces by Brink and Johnston in Dancy, ed. (1997). Rounding off your work on Kant, you might also want to think about his attempt at ambitious vindication. See section III of the Groundwork as well as the discussion in Part IV of Allison (2011) and Ch. 6 of Korsgaard (1996), both listed in the CORE READING for THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE. For a recent attempt at ambitious vindication, see de Lazari-Radek and Singer (2014). Think also about Hills’ own modest vindication, which is usefully contrasted with Prichard (1912). Psychological egoism also poses problems. Insofar as ought implies can, it appears to imply rational egoism, or something much like it. But it also seems to imply, more directly, that, even where one can do the right thing, one cannot do it for the right reasons. In thinking about it more, see, in addition to Blackburn’s piece in the CORE READING, Sober’s contribution to LaFollette and Persson and Stich, Doris, and Roedder (2010). Also take a look at the early modern debate, especially Butler’s argument against psychological egoism in Sermon XI of his (1726) Fifteen Sermons at the Rolls Chapel, and Hume’s very similar treatment of the issues in Appendix 2 of his Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, listed as Hume (1751/77) in the FURTHER READING for HUME’S ETHICS. For an important later discussion, key background to many contemporary formulations of the problems hereabouts, see Sidgwick (1907), who hoped to show that rational egoism and utilitarianism can be reconciled, but couldn’t see how without appeal to God. For discussions of a range of relevant issues, contemporary and historical, see also Bloomfield, ed. (2007).

Bloomfield, Paul, ed. (2007) Morality and Self-Interest (OUP).

Butler, Joseph (1726) Fifteen Sermons at the Rolls Chapel, esp. Sermon XI. Various editions, including Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel: And Other Writings on Ethics, edited by David McNaughton (OUP, 2017). Relevant extracts are also reprinted in Cahn and Markie and Raphael.

Dancy, Jonathan, ed. (1997) Reading Parfit (Blackwell). This doesn't seem to be available online, but Brink's paper is available here: https://davidobrink.com/publication/rational-egoism-and-separateness-persons

Hobbes, Thomas (1651) Leviathan, Ch. 13 to 15. Various editions, including Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought, revised student edition, ed. by Richard Tuck (Cambridge UP, 1996). Relevant extracts are also reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Raphael, Shafer-Landau, and Sher.

de Lazari-Radek, Katarzyna and Peter Singer (2014) The Point of View of the Universe: Sidgwick and Contemporary Ethics (OUP), Ch. 7. See also Ch. 6, discussing Sidgwick, Parfit, and others.

Parfit, Derek (1984) Reasons and Persons (OUP), pp. 1-24, 87-95, Part II, and Part III (esp. Ch. 14).

Raz, Joseph (1999) Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action (OUP), Ch. 11 to 13.

Sidgwick, Henry (1907) Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Macmillan), Bk. IV, Ch. II and Concluding Chapter.

Stich, Stephen, John. M. Doris, and Erica Roedder (2010) ‘Altruism’ in John M. Doris, ed., The Moral Psychology Handbook (OUP).

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘Far from being able to assess the relative value of options for an agent by their possible contribution to his well-being, we cannot judge their contribution to his well-being except by reference to their value.’ (JOSEPH RAZ) Is this the basis of a successful response to the amoralist? (2022)

EITHER
(a) ‘There is no essential conflict between morality and self-interest because a good life is one that involves attention to the interests of others.’ Discuss.
OR
(b) ‘A person’s virtues are called good with respect to their presumed effects not on him but on us and society—the praise of virtues has always been far from “selfless”, far from “unegoistic”! […] The neighbour praises selflessness because it brings him advantages! […] Hereby we hint at the fundamental contradiction in the morality that is very much honoured just now: the motives to this morality stand in opposition to its principle!’ (NIETZSCHE) Discuss. (2021)

‘The answer to the question “Why be prudent?” is neither more nor less clear than the answer to the question “Why be moral?”’ Is that true? What does your answer imply, if anything, about the plausibility of egoism as opposed to moralism? (2020)

‘The egoist believes that whether some future person will be me is crucial to whether I should care about that person’s well-being. But personal identity is not so important as all that.’ Discuss. (2019)

6. CONTRACTUALISM

TOP

This week, building on what we’ve learnt so far, we return to contemporary normative ethics, and take a look at one of the most interesting developments in nonconsequentialist thought, T. M. Scanlon’s contractualism.

ESSAY QUESTION

Does Scanlon’s contractualism provide a compelling account of moral wrongness?

CORE READING

Start by reading the following classics on the topic:

Scanlon, T. M. (Tim) (1998) What We Owe to Each Other (Harvard UP), Ch. 4 and 5. If you are pushed for time, focus for now on pp. 147-71 and pp. 229-41, and leave the rest for FURTHER READING.

Parfit, Derek (2003) ‘Justifiability to Each Person’ in Ratio 16(4), pp. 368-90. Note that there is an unfortunate misprint on p. 381. The numbers for Case Two should be 100, 100; 100, 90; and 0, 100.

Raz, Joseph (2022) ‘Normativity and the Other’ in his The Roots of Normativity, ed. by Ulrike Heuer (OUP). This is quite hard, and don't feel obliged to get on top of it now, but return to it later if you don't.

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Ashford, Elizabeth and Tim Mulgan (2007/18) ‘Contractualism’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 edition). A good, accessible introduction to contractualism and its main problems.

*Southwood, Nicholas (2009) ‘Moral Contractualism’ in Philosophy Compass 4(6), pp. 926–37. Another good, accessible introduction to Scanlon's contractualism, discussing the main arguments for and against it.

*Suikkanen, Jussi (2020) Contractualism (Cambridge UP), Ch. 2 and 3. An excellent, accessible introduction, discussing Scanlon's contractualism, its motivations, and the main objections that are raised against it.

*Wallace, R. Jay (2002) ‘Scanlon’s Contractualism’ in Ethics 112(3), pp. 429–70. A good survey piece, but written for professional philosophers, and so perhaps less accessible than other introductions.

FURTHER READING

Scanlon first presented his contractualism in a (1982) paper, written whilst visiting Oxford. He continued a long and fruitful debate with Parfit, who was sympathetic to the position but argued we’d do better to drop aspects of Scanlon’s version of it. See, in addition to Parfit (2003), Scanlon’s reply in the same issue of Ratio, which is a special issue devoted to What We Owe To Each Other. See also Ch. 15 and 17 of Parfit (2011a), listed above as FURTHER READING for CONSEQUENTIALISM and ITS CRITICS, in which he defends a variant form of contractualism (which he thinks coincides with both a kind of consequentialism and a kind of Kantianism). Then see Scanlon’s reply to the arguments of Parfit (2011a), ‘How I Am Not a Kantian,’ in Parfit (2011b), as well as Parfit’s own Ch. 21, 22, and 23. The latest instalments of the debate are in Stepanians and Frauchiger, eds. (2021), which includes Scanlon’s latest formulation of his views, ‘Contractualism and Justification,’ a critical paper by Parfit—sadly his last on the topic, delivered a few months before he died—and a reply from Scanlon. One of the main issues concerns the place of aggregation in contractualism. Recent work often focuses on the problems posed by cases involving risk. See Frick (2015), defending an ex ante solution. A related issue concerns demandingness. See Ashford (2003) and, for a reply that discusses contractualism’s implications for non-human animals, Hills (2010). For work on contractualism and deontology, see Kamm (2007). For more on the contractualist account of why we should be moral, see Scanlon (2008), esp. Ch. 4, listed in the FURTHER READING for THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE. Also relevant here is Lenman (2006). Lastly, for discussion of so-called redundancy objections, see Southwood (2010).

Ashford, Elizabeth (2003) ‘The Demandingness of Scanlon’s Contractualism’ in Ethics 113(2), pp. 273–302.

Frick, Johann (2015) ‘Contractualism and Social Risk’ in Philosophy and Public Affairs 43(3), pp. 175–223.

Hills, Alison (2010) ‘Utilitarianism, Contractualism and DemandingnessThe Philosophical Quarterly 60(239), pp. 225–242.

Kamm, F. M. (Frances Myrna) (2007) Intricate Ethics (OUP), Ch. 16, esp. pp. 470-4.

Lenman, James (2006) ‘Compatibilism and Contractualism: The Possibility of Moral Responsibility’ in Ethics 117(1), pp. 7–31.

Parfit, Derek (2011b) On What Matters, Volume 2 (OUP).

Scanlon, T. M. (Tim) (1982) ‘Contractualism and Utilitarianism’ in Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, eds. Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge UP). Reprinted in his (2003) The Difficulty of Tolerance: Essays in Political Philosophy (Cambridge UP), Cahn and Markie, Shafer-Landau, and Sher.

Southwood, Nicholas (2010) Contractualism and the Foundations of Morality (OUP), Ch. 7.

Stepanians, Markus, and Michael Frauchiger, eds. (2021) Reason, Justification, and Contractualism (De Gruyter).

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘When I reflect on the reason that the wrongness of an action seems to supply not to do it, the best description of this reason I can come up with has to do with the relation to others that such acts would put me in: the sense that others could reasonably object to what I do.’ (T. M. SCANLON) How powerful an argument for contractualism is this? (2022)

Are the objections to ‘common-sense’ moral principles that can be made by those in dire straits stronger than the objections to more demanding alternative principles that can be made by the better off? Discuss the implications of your answer for contractualism. (2021)

‘Contractualists tie the wrongness of an action to whether all principles for the general regulation of behavior which permit it can be reasonably rejected. However, whatever explains why those principles can be reasonably rejected can on its own explain why the action is wrong. So, contractualists should drop the talk about reasonable rejection and just talk about what makes actions right or wrong.’ Do you agree? (2020)

Does contractualism imply that we have no obligations to beings who do not understand what it means to enter into a contract? What does your answer imply about the plausibility of contractualism? (2019)

7. VIRTUE ETHICS

TOP

Concluding our look at contemporary normative ethics, we look at virtue ethics, which emerged out of twentieth century criticism of consequentialism and deontology, and promises an alternative to both.

ESSAY QUESTION

Are virtue ethicists right to make virtue fundamental in ethical theory?

CORE READING

Start by reading the following classics on the topic:

Anscombe, G. E. M. (Elizabeth) (1958) ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ in Philosophy 33(124), pp. 1-19. Reprinted in her (1981) Collected Philosophical Papers, Volume 3 (Blackwell) and Roger Crisp and Michael Slote, eds. (1997) Virtue Ethics (OUP), referred to below as Crisp and Slote, as well as in Cahn and Markie.

Hursthouse, Rosalind (1999) On Virtue Ethics (OUP), Ch. 1. Reprinted as ‘Virtue Ethics’ in Sher.

Hurka, Thomas (2001) Virtue, Vice, and Value (OUP), Ch. 8.

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Annas, Julia (2006) ‘Virtue Ethics’ in Copp. An excellent, albeit fairly advanced and partisan introduction to virtue ethics from one of its leading theorists, replying to some of the main objections raised against it.

*Hursthouse, Rosalind and Glenn Pettigrove (2003/16) ‘Virtue Ethics’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 edition). An accessible introduction to the main issues.

*Slote, Michael (2013) ‘Virtue Ethics’ in LaFollette and Persson. A good introduction to virtue ethics from another of its leading proponents, discussing its history, its different forms, and the main objections.

*Timmons, Mark (2012) Moral Theory: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Rowman & Littlefield), Ch. 10. A textbook discussion of the problems and prospects of contemporary virtue ethics and its Aristotelian roots.

FURTHER READING

If you are planning on working on virtue ethics in more depth, Crisp and Slote is invaluable, collecting together various influential classics. Besides the Anscombe, see especially McIntyre’s ‘The Nature of the Virtues’, McDowell’s ‘Virtue and Reason’, and Foot’s ‘Virtues and Vices’, though Williams’ ‘Morality, the Peculiar Institution’, Stocker’s ‘The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories’, Wolf’s ‘Moral Saints’ (also reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Shafer-Landau, and Sher), and Murdoch’s ‘The Sovereignty of the Good over Other Concepts’ are also influential classics from the 70s and early 80s, and very much worth reading. Much of this early work is broadly Aristotelian in outlook—Murdoch’s more Platonic approach is a rare exception—and Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics is essential reading, regardless of whether you plan on working on the topic in any depth, really. (Relevant extracts are reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Shafer-Landau, and Sher.) More recent work has developed alternative ways of thinking about virtue ethics. See, for example, the agent-based approach—influenced by Hume and other early modern sentimentalists—of Slote in his piece, ‘Agent-Based Virtue Ethics,’ in Crisp and Slote (and reprinted in Shafer-Landau,) and the pluralistic, target-centred approach presented in Swanton (2003). Many early virtue ethicists attacked the idea that moral deliberation could be understood in terms of a codifiable decision procedure—a theme that is especially prominent in McDowell and Williams, but which gave rise to the objection that virtue ethics is not action-guiding. Relatedly, it is objected that virtue ethics does not provide an adequate account of right action, failing either to correctly identify which acts are right in the first place, or to provide an adequate explanation of what makes them right. (Also related is the objection that virtue ethics entails a problematic MORAL RELATIVISM.) See Johnson (2003) and, for a reply, see Annas (2004). See also Brewer (2009), insisting such objections rest on an assumption about right, wrong, and obligation that the original virtue ethicists—especially Anscombe—were concerned to reject. Other objections to think about include the worry that virtue ethics is problematically self-effacing—see Keller (2007)—or egoistic—see Annas’s paper, ‘Virtue Ethics and the Charge of Egoism,’ in Bloomfield, ed. (2007), listed in the FURTHER READING for EGOISM: WHY BE MORAL?. For some discussion of the paradox of deontology relating to the latter worry, see LeBar (2009). Think also about the justification problem, how to justify claims about which traits are virtues, and the sceptical threat posed by results in social psychology suggesting there is no such thing as character traits—the so-called situationist critique. The latter objection is pressed by Harman (1999), among others. For a reply, try Kamtekar (2004).

Annas, Julia (2004) ‘Being Virtuous and Doing the Right Thing’ in Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 78, pp. 61–74. Reprinted in Cahn and Markie and Shafer-Landau.

Brewer, Talbot (2009) The Retrieval of Ethics (OUP).

Harman, Gilbert (1999) ‘Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error’ in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99, pp. 315–331.

Johnson, Robert (2003) ‘Virtue and Right’ in Ethics 113(4), pp. 810–834.

Kamtekar, Rachana (2004) ‘Situationism and Virtue Ethics on the Content of Our Character’ in Ethics 114(3), pp. 458–91.

Keller, Simon (2007) ‘Virtue Ethics Is Self-Effacing’ in Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85(2), pp. 221–31.

Lebar, Mark (2009) ‘Virtue Ethics and Deontic Constraints’ in Ethics 119(4), pp. 642–671.

Swanton, Christine (2003) Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View (OUP).

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

Must virtue ethics be objectionably self-effacing? (2022)

‘Virtue ethics is an attractive account of the value of acting virtuously, but it has nothing distinctive to say about moral obligation in particular.’ Discuss. (2021)

EITHER
(a) ‘Since virtues can conflict in difficult situations, virtue ethics cannot guide us in those circumstances in which we most need moral theory.’ Is that right? Does it tell against virtue ethics as a moral theory?
OR
(b) ‘It is virtuous to tell someone the truth because they deserve it; it is not that they deserve it because it is virtuous to tell them the truth.’ If that is true, would it be a problem for virtue ethics? (2020)

Are virtue ethicists committed to the view that those who find it easier to be good are more praiseworthy for being good? What does your answer imply about the plausibility of virtue ethics? (2019)

8. MORAL REALISM: PROBLEMS

TOP

We finish with an introduction to metaethics, looking at some classic problems for moral realism, the view (roughly) that first-order moral claims are truth-apt, i.e. aim to state facts, and, in some cases, succeed.

ESSAY QUESTION

What are the main arguments against moral realism? Are any of them compelling?

CORE READING

Focus on these classics of twentieth century metaethics:

Moore, G. E. (1903) Principia Ethica (Cambridge UP), Ch. 1, ‘The Subject-Matter of Ethics’, §§1-15. Reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Fisher and Kirchin, Shafer-Landau, and Sher.

Ayer, A. J. (1936) Language, Truth, and Logic (Victor Gollanz), Ch. 6, ‘Critique of Ethics and Theology,’ esp. pp. 104-9. Reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Sayre-McCord, Shafer-Landau, and Sher.

Mackie, J. L. (1977) Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Penguin), Ch. 1. Reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, Fisher and Kirchin, Sayre-McCord, Shafer-Landau, and Sher.

Harman, Gilbert (1977) The Nature of Morality (OUP), Ch. 1, ‘Ethics and Observation’. Reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, Sayre-McCord, Shafer-Landau, and Sher.

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Darwall, Stephen (1998) Philosophical Ethics (Westview), Ch. 2 and 3. An accessible introduction to ethical naturalism, Harman's explanatory challenge, and Moore's open question argument.

*Fisher, Andrew (2011) Metaethics: An Introduction (Acumen), Ch. 1 to 3. An accessible introduction to Moore's open question argument, Ayer's emotivism, and Mackie's error theory.

*Kirchin, Simon (2012) Metaethics (Palgrave Macmillan), Ch. 1 to 3, up to p. 48. Another accessible introduction, discussing moral realism, Moore's open question argument, and naturalism.

*Miller, Alexander (2013) Contemporary Metaethics: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Polity), Ch. 1 to 3. An advanced introduction to the open question argument and Ayer's case against nonnaturalism.

*Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey (2005/15) ‘Moral Realism’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 edition). An accessible overview of the debate about moral realism.

*Roojen, Mark van (2015) Metaethics: A Contemporary Introduction (Routledge), Ch. 1 to 3. Another advanced introduction, discussing Mackie and Moore, as well as Harman's challenge.

FURTHER READING

Other introductory discussions of this week’s issues include Smith’s contribution to LaFollette and Persson and Sayre-McCord’s to Copp. Frankena (1939) and Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton (1992) are two classics on the open question argument, and must reads. Other, more recent discussions include Rosati (1995) and Kalderon (2004). For more on intuitionism, see Tropman (2009) and the papers in Stratton-Lake, ed. (2003).

Note that this week’s topic is best studied in conjunction with others in metaethics. See ERROR THEORY and FICTIONALISM for more on views like Mackie’s, and NONCOGNITIVISM for more on views like Ayer’s. For more on the sort of realism attacked by Moore and Harman, see NATURALISM. For more on the sort of realism defended by Moore, and attacked by Mackie and Ayer, see NONNATURALISM—a view that has come back into fashion lately. Lastly, for Harman’s positive views in metaethics, see MORAL RELATIVISM.

Darwall, Stephen, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton (1992) ‘Toward Fin de Siècle Ethics: Some Trends’ in The Philosophical Review 101(1), pp. 115–89. Reprinted in Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton.

Frankena, William (1939) ‘The Naturalistic Fallacy’ in Mind 48(192), pp. 464–77. Reprinted in Fisher and Kirchin.

Kalderon, Mark Eli (2004) ‘Open Questions and the Manifest Image’ in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68(2), pp. 251–89.

Rosati, Connie S. (1995) ‘Naturalism, Normativity, and the Open Question Argument’ in Noûs 29(1), pp. 46-70.

Stratton-Lake, Philip, ed. (2003) Ethical Intuitionism: Re-evaluations (OUP).

Tropman, Elizabeth (2009) ‘Renewing Moral Intuitionism’ in Journal of Moral Philosophy 6(4), pp. 440–63.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘Moral properties are just a highly unusual kind of natural property.’ Do you agree? (2022)

‘If it is a fact that a certain action would be good, a fact that you might or might not apply in deliberation, then it seems to be an open question whether you should apply it. So moral realism does not correctly capture the relation between the deliberative process and the normative standards to which action is subject.’ Is this argument against moral realism any good? (2021)

‘If we deny realism about moral facts, we must by parity of reasoning deny it about mathematical and epistemological facts. That would be unacceptable. So, we should not deny realism about moral facts.’ Is this a good argument? (2020)

EITHER
(a) Does moral realism predict that there should be more agreement about ethics than there is? What does your answer imply about the plausibility of moral realism?
OR
(b) ‘Morality is a useful fiction.’ Do you agree? (2019)

OTHER TOPICS: METAETHICS

1. ERROR THEORY and FICTIONALISM

TOP

ESSAY QUESTION

Should we be error theorists about morality? If so, should we also be abolitionists about morality?

CORE READING

If you haven’t already, read the following classic exposition and defence of error theory:

Mackie, J. L. (1977) Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Penguin), Ch. 1. Reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, Fisher and Kirchin, Sayre-McCord, Shafer-Landau, and Sher. Ch. 5 is also relevant, if you have time—though not reprinted in any of the foregoing.

If you have already read the Mackie, take a look at the following, long-unpublished classic:

Burgess, John P. (2007) ‘Against Ethics’ in Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10(5), pp. 427-39. Reprinted in Richard Joyce and Simon Kirchin, eds. (2010) A World Without Values (Springer).

Then read the following, more recent discussions of the issues:

Joyce, Richard (2005) ‘Moral Fictionalism’ in Mark Eli Kalderon, ed. Fictionalism in Metaphysics (OUP). Reprinted in his (2016) Essays in Moral Skepticism (OUP).

West, Catherine (2010) ‘Business as Usual? The Error Theory, Internalism, and the Function of Morality’ in Richard Joyce and Simon Kirchin, eds. (2010) A World Without Values (Springer).

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Fisher, Andrew (2011) Metaethics: An Introduction (Acumen), Ch. 3 and 10. Good, accessible discussions of both error theory, focusing on Mackie's arguments for it, and fictionalism.

*Joyce, Richard (2007/21) ‘Moral Anti-Realism’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 edition). An overview of moral anti-realism, including error theory.

*Kirchin, Simon (2012) Metaethics (Palgrave Macmillan), Ch. 4. Another accessible introduction to error theor, discussing both arguments for it and various solutions to the now what? problem.

*Miller, Alexander (2013) Contemporary Metaethics: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Polity), Ch. 6. An excellent, albeit more advanced introduction to error theory. Particularly recommended.

*Roojen, Mark van (2015) Metaethics: A Contemporary Introduction (Routledge), Ch. 5. Another good, albeit advanced introduction to error theory. See also Ch. 9, on fictionalism.

*Vavova, Katia (2015) ‘Evolutionary Debunking of Moral Realism’ in Philosophy Compass 10(2), pp. 104–16. A good introduction to the debate over so-called evolutionary debunking arguments.

FURTHER READING

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘There are no objective moral values, but we should nevertheless pretend that they exist.’ Do you agree? (2022)

Can evolutionary debunking arguments in ethics be answered by appealing to evolutionary pressures that favour the capacity to make accurate moral judgments? (2021)

Do facts about evolution matter for an account of the nature of moral facts? (2020)

EITHER
(a) Does moral realism predict that there should be more agreement about ethics than there is? What does your answer imply about the plausibility of moral realism?
OR
(b) ‘Morality is a useful fiction.’ Do you agree? (2019)

2. NON-COGNITIVISM and QUASI-REALISM

TOP

ESSAY QUESTION

What is the Frege-Geach problem for noncognitivism? How, if at all, should it be solved?

CORE READING

Read the following contemporary classics on noncognitivism:

Blackburn, Simon (1984) Spreading the Word (OUP), Ch. 5 and Ch. 6, §§2 and 3. Reprinted in Fisher and Kirchin as ‘Realism and Variations’ and ‘The Frege-Geach Problem’ respectively.

Roojen, Mark van (1996) ‘Expressivism and Irrationality’ in The Philosophical Review 105(3), pp. 311-35.

If you have the time, reading the following as well:

Gibbard, Allan (2003) Thinking How To Live (Harvard UP), Ch. 3 and 4.

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Fisher, Andrew (2011) Metaethics: An Introduction (Acumen), Ch. 6. An accessible introduction to the Frege-Geach problem for noncognitivism, Blackburn's quasi-realism, and the wider debate.

*Joyce, Richard (2007/21) ‘Moral Anti-Realism’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 edition). An overview of moral anti-realism, including noncognitivism.

*Kirchin, Simon (2012) Metaethics (Palgrave Macmillan), Ch. 5. An introduction to noncognitivism, the main arguments for it, and the main objections to it, including the Frege-Geach problem.

*Miller, Alexander (2013) Contemporary Metaethics: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Polity), Ch. 3 to 5. A great, advanced introduction, discussing emotivism and Frege-Geach, Blackburn, and Gibbard.

*Roojen, Mark van (2015) Metaethics: A Contemporary Introduction (Routledge), Ch. 8. Another good introduction, covering noncognitivism, the Frege-Geach problem, and other issues.

*Schroeder, Mark (2008) ‘What is the Frege-Geach Problem?’ in Philosophy Compass 3/4, pp. 703–720. An excellent overview of the Frege-Geach problem, and various attempts to solve it.

FURTHER READING

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘Arguments for non-cognitivism rely on a distinction between beliefs and non-cognitive attitudes, which any satisfactory solution to the Frege-Geach problem will undermine.’ Is this a decisive objection to non-cognitivism? (2022)

EITHER
(a) Compare ‘Hirst has produced some bad art’ with ‘Hirst has done some bad things’. Can the non-cognitivist plausibly account for the fact that these express different kinds of normative judgment?
OR
(b) Should we analyse moral sentences on the model of pejoratives, as essentially involving both beliefs and non-cognitive attitudes? (2021)

Can a non-cognitivist think that she herself might be wrong about her most basic values? (2020)

Has the non-cognitivist anything plausible to say about what mental state is expressed by utterances of ‘If lying is wrong, then liars will be punished’? (2019)

3. NATURALISM

TOP

ESSAY QUESTION

Is any form of moral naturalism defensible?

CORE READING

Start with the following classic readings on the topic:

Sturgeon, Nicholas (1985) ‘Moral Explanations’ in David Copp and David Zimmerman, eds. Morality, Reason and Truth (Rowman & Allanheld). Reprinted in Cahn and Markie, Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, Fisher and Kirchin, Sayre-McCord, and Sher.

Horgan, Terence and Mark Timmons (1992) ‘Troubles for New Wave Moral Semantics: The “Open Question Argument” Revived’ in Philosophical Papers 21(3), pp. 153-75. Reprinted in Fisher and Kirchin.

Jackson, Frank, and Philip Pettit (1995) ‘Moral Functionalism and Moral Motivation’ in The Philosophical Quarterly 45(178), pp. 20-40. Reprinted in Frank Jackson, Philip Pettit, and Michael Smith (2004) Mind, Morality, and Explanation: Selected Collaborations (OUP).

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Fisher, Andrew (2011) Metaethics: An Introduction (Acumen), Ch. 4. An accessible introduction to the debate over moral naturalism, focusing on the Canberra Plan and synthetic realism.

*Kirchin, Simon (2012) Metaethics (Palgrave Macmillan), Ch. 3, p. 48 onwards. Another accessible introduction to moral realism, discussing nonreductive and reductive forms of naturalism.

*Little, Margaret (1994) ‘Moral Realism I: Naturalism’ in Philosophical Books 35(3), pp. 145–53. A brief, accessible introduction to the contemporary debate over the prospects for naturalism.

*Lutz, Matt and James Lenman (2006/18) ‘Moral Naturalism’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 edition). A good introduction to the main issues.

*Miller, Alexander (2013) Contemporary Metaethics: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Polity), Ch. 8 and 9. A good, advanced introduction to nonreductive and reductive forms of moral naturalism.

*van Roojen, Mark (2015) Metaethics: A Contemporary Introduction (Routledge), Ch. 11 to 13. A good, advanced introduction to nonanalytic (i.e. synthetic) and analytic forms of moral naturalism.

FURTHER READING

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘Moral properties are just a highly unusual kind of natural property.’ Do you agree? (2022)

‘If it is a fact that a certain action would be good, a fact that you might or might not apply in deliberation, then it seems to be an open question whether you should apply it. So moral realism does not correctly capture the relation between the deliberative process and the normative standards to which action is subject.’ Is this argument against moral realism any good? (2021)

‘If we deny realism about moral facts, we must by parity of reasoning deny it about mathematical and epistemological facts. That would be unacceptable. So, we should not deny realism about moral facts.’ Is this a good argument? (2020)

EITHER
(a) Does moral realism predict that there should be more agreement about ethics than there is? What does your answer imply about the plausibility of moral realism?
OR
(b) ‘Morality is a useful fiction.’ Do you agree? (2019)

4. NONNATURALISM

TOP

ESSAY QUESTION

Is there any compelling argument for moral nonnaturalism? How, if at all, can moral nonnaturalists explain the supervenience of moral properties on natural properties?

CORE READING

Start with the following classic readings on the topic:

McDowell, John (1985) ‘Values and Secondary Qualities’ in Ted Honderich, ed. Morality and Objectivity (Routledge). Reprinted in his (1998) Mind, Value, and Reality (Harvard UP), as well as Cahn and Markie, Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, Fisher and Kirchin, and Sayre-McCord.

Enoch, David (2011) Taking Morality Seriously: A Defence of Robust Realism (OUP), Ch. 3.

Scanlon, T. M. (2014) Being Realistic about Reasons (OUP), Ch. 1 and 2.

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Cuneo, Terence (2007) ‘Recent Faces of Moral Nonnaturalism’ in Philosophy Compass 2(6), pp. 850–79. A good, accessible survey piece, discussing contemporary work on nonnaturalism.

*Fisher, Andrew (2011) Metaethics: An Introduction (Acumen), Ch. 5. A good discussion of nonnaturalism, discussing divine command theories and Shafer-Landau's nonreductionism.

*Kirchin, Simon (2012) Metaethics (Palgrave Macmillan), Ch. 6. A good, accessible introduction to sensibility theories, like McDowell's, discussing, among other things, the supervenience problem.

*Miller, Alexander (2013) Contemporary Metaethics: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Polity), Ch. 10. Another good, albeit advanced introduction to McDowell's sensibility theory.

*Ridge, Michael (2003/19) ‘Moral Non-naturalism’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 edition). An excellent, if advanced overview of the central issues.

*van Roojen, Mark (2015) Metaethics: A Contemporary Introduction (Routledge), Ch. 13. An excellent introduction to arguments for and against nonnaturalism, including supervenience.

FURTHER READING

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘Moral properties are just a highly unusual kind of natural property.’ Do you agree? (2022)

‘If it is a fact that a certain action would be good, a fact that you might or might not apply in deliberation, then it seems to be an open question whether you should apply it. So moral realism does not correctly capture the relation between the deliberative process and the normative standards to which action is subject.’ Is this argument against moral realism any good? (2021)

‘If we deny realism about moral facts, we must by parity of reasoning deny it about mathematical and epistemological facts. That would be unacceptable. So, we should not deny realism about moral facts.’ Is this a good argument? (2020)

EITHER
(a) Does moral realism predict that there should be more agreement about ethics than there is? What does your answer imply about the plausibility of moral realism?
OR
(b) ‘Morality is a useful fiction.’ Do you agree? (2019)

5. MORAL RELATIVISM

TOP

ESSAY QUESTION

CORE READING

Start with the following classic readings on the topic:

Harman, Gilbert (1975) ‘Moral Relativism Defended’ in The Philosophical Review 85(1), pp. 3-22. Reprinted in his (2000) Explaining Value: And Other Essays in Moral Philosophy (OUP).

Lyons, David (1976) ‘Ethical Relativism and the Problem of Incoherence’ in Ethics 86(2), pp. 107–21.

Foot, Philippa (1979) ‘Moral Relativism,’ The Lindley Lecture, Department of Philosophy, University of Kansas. Reprinted in her (2002) Moral Dilemmas: and Other Topics in Moral Philosophy (OUP).

By way of a guide, try any of the following introductory discussions—you needn’t read them all:

*Fisher, Andrew (2011) Metaethics: An Introduction (Acumen), Ch. 7. An accessible introduction to the main forms of moral relativism, and some of the arguments for and against them.

*Francén Olinder, Ragnar (2016) ‘Some Varieties of Metaethical Relativism’ in Philosophy Compass 11(10), pp. 529–40. An “opiniated survey article” discussing so-called appraiser relativism.

*Gowans, Christopher (2004/15) ‘Moral Relativism’ in Edward Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 edition). A good, comprehensive survey article on the issues.

*Moser, Paul K. and Thomas L. Carson (2000) ‘Introduction’ to Paul K. Moser and Thomas L. Carson, eds. Moral Relativism (OUP). A good introduction to the debate over moral relativism.

FURTHER READING

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

Is moral relativism a good explanation of the existence of widespread moral disagreement? (2022)

Can a moral relativist give a compelling account of cross-cultural moral criticism? (2021)

EITHER
(a) If morality is relative to something, what is it relative to?
OR
(b) ‘If we’re cognitivists about ethics, we’ll have to be either realists or relativists.’ Do you agree? (2020)

What is the best objection to meta-ethical relativism? Does it succeed? (2019)

OTHER TOPICS: REASONS and MOTIVES

1. PRACTICAL REASONING

TOP

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

Can internalism about practical reasons makes sense of the critical dimension of claims about what reasons an agent has? (2022)

‘If there are only internal reasons for action, then there is no external reason to want to know all the salient non-moral facts. But in that case, in failing to take account of one of those facts in practical deliberation one needn’t be making a mistake.’ Is this a good objection to internalism about normative reasons for action? (2021)

EITHER
(a) ‘As experience can reveal reasons to believe something for which I previously had absolutely no evidence, so it can reveal reasons to do something which I previously was utterly unmotivated to do.’ Is that true? If not, why not? If so, what does it imply about the internalism/externalism debate about reasons?
OR
(b) If an act is morally obligatory, does it follow that it would be irrational not to perform it? (2020)

EITHER
(a) Is motivational externalism committed to viewing good and strong-willed people as in the grip of moral fetishism? OR
(b) Could moral beliefs be intrinsically motivating? (2019)

2. MOTIVATIONAL INTERNALISM

TOP

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

EITHER
(a) Is motivational externalism committed to viewing good and strong-willed people as in the grip of moral fetishism?
OR
(b) Could moral beliefs be intrinsically motivating? (2019)

‘It’s a happy accident that, if I come to believe that some act is wrong, a corresponding desire not to do that act invariably follows. And most people are like me in this respect.’ Is this an adequate account of moral motivation? (2017)

‘Evil, be thou my good’. Can motivational internalism make sense of this? (2016)

Is a desire to do the right thing, simply because it is right, fetishistic in any objectionable sense? (2015)

OTHER TOPICS: NORMATIVE ETHICS

1. WELL-BEING

TOP

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘Hedonism is merely an arbitrarily short version of the objective list theory of wellbeing, and moreover one that can’t avail itself of a perfectionist rationale.’ Is this a compelling reason to favour the objective list theory over hedonism? (2022)

‘As a theory of which things make a person’s life go well, the objective list account is attractive. But, unlike its competitors, this account does not adequately explain what makes them good.’ Assess. (2021)

Does wanting something suffice to make it good for you to get it? (2020)

Does welfare consist in desire satisfaction? (2019)

2. EQUALITY

TOP

ESSAY QUESTION

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

Do egalitarians have any compelling answer to the Levelling Down Objection? (2022)

‘Unlike prioritarianism and sufficientarianism, egalitarianism can explain what’s bad about inequality.’ Is this a powerful argument for egalitarianism? (2021)

‘The important thing is not whether I have as much of some good as you but whether I have enough of it. Hence, equality is not in itself significant.’ Discuss. (2020)

‘Just as resources have diminishing marginal utility, so utility has diminishing marginal moral importance.’ (DEREK PARFIT) Does it? (2019)

3. RIGHTS

TOP

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

Is it possible to wrong someone without violating any of their moral rights? (2022)

In what way are the duties imposed by rights distinctive? (2021)

Can there be a right to do wrong? (2020)

‘There is no need to postulate rights in addition to obligations.’ Is that correct? (2019)

OTHER TOPICS: MORAL PSYCHOLOGY

1. FREE WILL and MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

TOP

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘Incompatibilists are fundamentally concerned about the fairness of holding people responsible, but the fairness of holding someone responsible has nothing to do with whether they were free in any strong sense.’ Is this a good argument for compatibilism? (2022)

‘We hold parents responsible for the behaviour of their children and leaders responsible for the behaviour of their followers. So we have no problem in principle with holding people responsible for what they do not control. Determinism is therefore no threat to the possibility of moral responsibility.’ Is this argument sound? (2021)

‘What matters for determining moral responsibility is why she did what she did, not whether she could have done something else.’ Is that right? (2020)

‘If a neuroscientist implanted electrodes in my brain and thereby induced in me attitudes that deterministically led me to wholeheartedly perform a certain crime, then she, and not I, would be morally responsible for the crime.’ Do you agree? What does your answer imply about the plausibility of compatibilism? (2019)

2. CONSCIENCE, GUILT, and SHAME

TOP

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

What, if anything, is wrong with being shameless? (2022)

Is guilt merely a subspecies of shame? (2021)

‘I’ll feel guilty whatever I do.’ Assume that there are situations where this can be true: does it follow that guilt is irrelevant to morality? (2020)

Is there any truth in Nietzsche’s suggestion that bad conscience is ‘cruelty turned back on itself’? (2018)

OTHER TOPICS: APPLIED ETHICS

1. DOING and INTENDING HARM

TOP

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

‘If the Doctrine of Double Effect were true, I could make a terror bombing permissible just by finding someone nice to do it for me.’ How compelling an objection to the Doctrine of Double Effect is this? (2022)

EITHER
(a) Can the Doctrine of Doing and Allowing be plausibly justified as a protection against morality’s problematically imposing upon agents?
OR
(b) Can the Trolley Problem be solved? (2018; SECTION B)

EITHER
(a) Is it ever permissible to kill an innocent bystander in self-defence?
OR
(b) Is it ever the case that an agent intends a harm if she views that harm as at best a regrettable necessity? What are the ethical implications of your answer? (2017)

‘The distinction between intended and foreseen but unintended consequences is real enough, but it cannot bear any moral weight.’ Discuss. (2012)

2. NON-HUMAN ANIMALS

TOP

Coming soon.

PAST PAPER QUESTIONS

Do animal rights stand in the way of our re-introducing predator species to ecosystems from which they have vanished in recent centuries? (2022)

‘The charge of speciesism depends for its power on a prior assumption of moral equality based on the capacity for suffering. But that capacity gets its distinctively moral significance from within an outlook that is essentially concerned with the attitudes humans bear to each other, and so cannot furnish the needed basis.’ Is this a compelling argument? (2021)

If you cannot save both, ought you to save a healthy adult pig loved by all or a healthy infant human being for whom no one feels any affection? (2020)

‘If animal suffering mattered in the way that animal rights theorists believe it does, then we would be obligated to alleviate wild animal suffering.’ Discuss. (2019)